Free Will
- Gyaneshwar Mishra
- May 25, 2024
- 7 min read
Updated: May 27, 2024
Not long ago, I was out with a friend, and we were in a car on our way to a decent place to satisfy our existential craving for abdominal fulfillment (food). The trip began with small talk and the normal (mostly political) arguments and current affairs, but somewhere in the middle of those arguments, the subject of free will arose.
I confidently asserted my belief that independent choices and free will are mere illusions. According to my perspective, our decisions, regardless of their apparent autonomy, are intricately woven into a fabric of dependencies and predetermined factors that subconsciously influence our choices. Our debate raged on for nearly three hours, taking us on two rounds through our city, our vehicular contribution to global warming becoming unintentionally significant by burning of the fossil fuels for avoidable driving.
My friend staunchly opposed my viewpoint, arguing that while on a grand scale, or what he termed as the "macro level," free will might be elusive, at the "micro level," absolute free will prevails. As our opinions clashed, and our arguments danced through the realms of logic, we found ourselves agreeing only on the fact that we held divergent thoughts on the matter.
While I stood firm in my belief that our choices are not free but rather guided by countless conscious and subconscious influences, my friend's stance centered around the idea that, at a microscopic level, we possess genuine free will. We mutually decided to temporarily halt our debate when exhaustion set in after three hours of continuous speaking and thinking. Instead, we shifted our focus to enjoying a pleasant meal at our tables. This lively debate spurred my curiosity, leading me to delve deeper into the concept of free will.
A few days later, we found ourselves returning from an event that commemorated the rich history along the Banks of Narmada. Our group, which included the friend I previously mentioned, decided to dine at another restaurant, this time with additional company beyond us two. I saw this as an opportune moment to engage in some mediation and discussion, anticipating that the presence of extra minds could serve as valuable arbiters or mediators, helping to resolve a debate I had with our friend earlier.
As we waited for our food to arrive, I introduced the topic for discussion. The initial speaker sided with our friend's perspective, momentarily dampening my spirits. However, my disappointment was short-lived as the other two participants expressed agreement with my viewpoint. With the tables once again divided, my determination to settle the debate persisted.
During this round of deliberation, something intriguing emerged. A group member suggested that while debates and discussions may never reach a conclusive end, both sides could potentially have valid perspectives, contingent on how one defines free will. This resonated with the teachings from our esteemed professors in Negotiation classes, emphasizing the importance of ensuring a proper, correct, and comprehensive understanding of the debated topic.
In my understanding, free will entails complete autonomy, devoid of any constraints, influences, or exposures that might impact my decision or choice-making process. It also implies liberation from preconceived biases or notions. Essentially, my will should be intrinsic and untainted by external influences, maintaining its purity and independence in absolute forms.
However, the feasibility of such a concept and its relevance in a given context come into question. How can one preserve their freedom and remain unadulterated amidst the billions of influences surrounding us? Consider a newborn, often described as being in a Tabula Rasa state, denoting the idea that individuals are born without inherent mental content, acquiring knowledge solely through later perceptions and sensory experiences. During this phase, there is an absence of preconceived notions or goals. Yet, as soon as a child is born and exposed to sensory stimuli, they become susceptible to external influences, leading to the gradual loss of any innate freedom or Free will they might possess.
To explain it further, Consider a scenario where an individual must select one of two transparent bottles to satisfy their thirst—one containing a colorless liquid and the other a red one. When the person makes a choice between these bottles, the question arises: where does the logic behind choosing one over the other originate? Is it not derived from past influences and decisions, a convergence of countless factors shaping the preference for one bottle over the other? In such a situation, can the term "free" or "independent" truly be ascribed to the choice, given the evident influence of myriad factors on the decision-making process?
Some may argue that the choice is still within their rational control, but this rationality and reasoning to choose a particular bottle must emerge from a process of internal logic and debate. However, it's essential to recognize that innate rationality and logic are not inherent; instead, individuals are born in a Tabula Rasa state and acquire knowledge through sensory perceptions. Therefore, the logic behind our choices is intricately tied to past experiences and exposures rather than an absolute exercise of free will.
In the debate over the existence of free will, proponents for the existence of free will center their arguments on the moral and practical dimensions that hinge on its presence. It's a topic that resonates with our daily lives, something so intrinsic that contemplating its absence seems almost counterintuitive.
Advocates of free will contend that humans possess the ability for conscious thought and reflection, enabling them to navigate decisions based on personal reasoning and values. The very act of conscious deliberation, they argue, is indicative of a form of free will. Supporters often draw attention to the subjective experience of freedom reported by individuals – that sense of empowerment when choosing and acting in alignment with one's desires serves as a tangible manifestation of free will.
However, the debate takes a more pragmatic turn when considering the implications of a world without free will. Take, for instance, the cornerstone of moral responsibility, which hinges on individuals having the capacity to distinguish between right and wrong. Proponents assert that without free will, holding individuals morally accountable becomes a challenge. This argument extends to the justice system. Legal systems, they argue, are built upon the assumption of free will, with criminal justice systems designed to hold individuals responsible for their actions, presupposing their capacity to make choices. Without free will, the argument concludes, criminals cannot be morally blamed for their actions, as the commission of a crime is not an independent choice.
The absence of free will also raises existential questions about the human experience. Proponents posit that the concept existence of free will lends life existential meaning and purpose. The ability to shape one's destiny and make meaningful choices contributes significantly to a sense of autonomy and fulfillment.
Yet, beyond the philosophical discourse, there is a practical convenience in assuming and internalizing the existence of free will. Advocates emphasize the importance of personal agency – the notion that individuals are active agents capable of initiating actions. This idea, they argue, is a fundamental aspect of human experience and clashes with a deterministic worldview.
Additionally, proponents underscore the practical benefits of embracing the concept of free will. It fosters individual responsibility, encouraging self-improvement and the development of ethical and moral values.
The age-old debate over the existence of free will remains a captivating subject, drawing on conflicting perspectives that challenge the very essence of human autonomy. Central to the skepticism surrounding free will is the deterministic viewpoint, which posits that all events, including human actions, unfold in accordance with the laws of nature. In a deterministic universe, the choices and actions of individuals are perceived as predetermined by antecedent events, questioning the authenticity of genuine free will.
Advancements in neuroscience contribute to the skepticism, suggesting that human actions are intricately linked to neural processes and biochemical reactions. This perspective implies that mental processes can be traced back to their physical counterparts, casting doubt on the concept of true freedom of choice. Additionally, the interplay of genetic factors and environmental influences emerges as a pivotal force shaping behavior. The argument here is that decisions are heavily influenced by genetics and the environment, challenging the idea of unfettered freedom in choice.
Various psychological factors may impact decision-making. Unconscious biases, emotions, and cognitive limitations are potential constraints, limiting individuals' full control over their choices and further eroding the concept of unrestricted free will. While some propose compatibilism as a reconciling perspective, acknowledging determinism but asserting the coexistence of free will, skeptics argue that the freedom allowed by compatibilism falls short of qualifying as genuine free will.
The case against free will gains complexity when considering inherent paradoxes and logical challenges within the concept. It is argued that the idea of an uncaused event, such as a truly random choice, is illogical and incomprehensible, adding another layer to the skepticism surrounding free will. Moreover, experiments like those conducted by Libet and subsequent neuroscience research challenge the conventional belief that conscious intentions are the primary drivers of actions. The revelation that brain activity associated with a decision precedes conscious awareness further undermines the foundation of free will.
External influences, including cultural and societal factors, are also introduced into the discussion. Critics contend that these influences play a powerful role in shaping individuals' values, beliefs, and choices. The argument posits that such external factors significantly curtail the range of choices available to individuals, restricting the scope of their free will.
As we make our way through the complex web of free will arguments, it becomes clear that the question is more of a path than a final destination. There is a wide range of viewpoints in the discussion of free will, and each one has important ethical, moral, and pragmatic consequences. Our free will is undermined by the deterministic perspective, which views our decisions as little more than a chain reaction in the grand scheme of things. Our judgments are intricately linked to the biochemical reactions and neuronal dance, and the latest discoveries in neuroscience only serve to deepen this intricacy.
A ray of hope for reconciliation does, however, appear amid this intellectual chaos. Free will and determinism, according to compatibilism's proponents, can live side by side in peace. It prompts us to consider a more sophisticated definition of autonomy, one that takes into account both internal and external factors, even though critics might see this as a middle ground rather than a final solution.
Uncaused events and conscious intents remain puzzling concepts, and the logical puzzles and paradoxes surrounding free will do not go away. Morality, justice, and the human experience itself are rock solid as we try to fathom what a world devoid of free choice may mean. The free will argument, rather than seeking a final resolution, is an investigation into the complexities inherent to human beings. Inquiry and thought are enriched simply by asking, arguing, and reflecting. No matter where one stands on the issue of free choice vs. determinism, the important thing is to seek understanding.
We must continue to wonder, contemplate, and participate in the never-ending discussion that characterizes our intellectual path as we wrap up this part of the continuing story about free choice.
Perhaps it is not in the categorical existence or absence of free will but in the deep investigation of the questions that form our conception of what it means to be genuinely free that we find its core, but rather in the dogged quest for knowledge.